Thursday 13 September 2012

Resurrection of resemblance theory



Has the Aristotelian “resemblance theory” of representation been abandoned, when we embark on a computational analysis of cognitive processes?  This question came to my mind when reading Geir Kirkebøen’s excellent article on “Descartes’ psychology of vision and cognitive science” (1998). I stumbled upon it after Fodor’s modularity book had sent me to reading texts on computational neuroscience and I came across David Marr’s influential book on vision (1982). It appeared posthumously after his death of leukaemia only at the age of 35. A reprint of the book has been issued quite recently. There are several good reviews of Marr’s conceptualisations.  Kirkebøen traces the historical antecedents of Marr’s view and demonstrates its similarity with Descartes’ theory of vision. This article, once again, demonstrates the immeasurable value of a historical approach to the theoretical issues of psychology. If you can get hold of this article, do read it.

Kirkebøen argues that Marr’s computational understanding is a restatement of Descartes’ solution to the problem, how  res extensa can become res cogitas. Descartes showed that extension (a “picture” on the retina) is transformed into mechanical movements in the optical nerve by a computational process that models two-dimensional objects like his analytical geometry modelled Euclidean forms.  This seems indeed to be the end of the “resemblance theory” of representations, as Fodor pointed out.

However, the idea that our visual perception uses algorithmic procedures to generate three-dimensional perceptibles from two-dimensional sense data does not abolish the problem of the relationship between the source and its retinal imprint. Oron Shagrir’s recent (2010) commentary on Marr’s theory is helpful here. The following quotations are terminologically difficult for us who are not trained in the language of computational neuroscience, but I believe you can recognise the point:

“In the case of edge detection, Marr (1982, 68ff.) refers to the constraint of spatial localization, which means (in this context) that the things in the world that give rise to intensity changes are spatially localized… Another pertinent physical fact is that intensity changes in the [retinal] image result from “surface discontinuities or from reflectance or illumination boundaries.” (Shagrir, 2010, p. 488)
“Marr’s explanation appeals to similarity between the internal mapping relations and external relations between the features that are being represented. The similarity is not at  the level of physical properties. After all, the physiological properties of the brain are quite different from the physical and optical properties that make up our visual field. The similarity is at a more abstract level of mathematical properties.” (p. 489)
“Thus, Marr not only demonstrates that the internal mathematical function correlates with the contingent world that we live in. He also underscores the basis of this correlation, which is a similarity of mathematical structures. This mathematically based similarity, I maintain, is the key in addressing the appropriateness problem…” (p. 489)
Shagrir does not refer to Kirkebøen’s paper and is perhaps not familiar with it. The second quotation, however, reproduces almost literally the Cartesian solution to the difference between the optic imprint and the physiological properties  of the brain. The similarity is established by mathematical modelling. To me this is a restatement of the resemblance theory. It is still about “form without matter” even if the form is not any more understood in pictorial terms. Shagrir also restates Aristotle's idea that vision is about distinguishing light from darkness.